Friday 12 June 2015

Death Penalty; A Pakistani Perspective







CAN LEGAL FICTION OVERCOME RELIGIOUS AND CONSTITUTIONAL LOCKS?



DEATH PENALTY: A PAKISTANI PERSPECTIVE


BY

Tipu Salman Makhdoom*





Abstract:
Death Penalty is not really an issue in Pakistan. Mostly because it’s an ideological state, Constitutionally having a religion which clearly provides for death penalty. In addition to this ideological check, there is also a Constitutional check. Constitution of Pakistan states that all laws need to confirm to Islam and Supreme Court of Pakistan says that among others, this part of Constitution constitutes the ‘Basic Structure’ of the Constitution which cannot be amended, even by adopting the procedure that Constitution itself provides for its amendment!
After making a jurisprudential argument in favour of abolition of death penalty, this paper explores the ideological and Constitutional checks in Pakistan legal system locking the death penalty in the system. In the end, an argument is made that in addition to taking the political course, a legal path can be taken to abolish the death penalty in Pakistan, without violating the Constitutional check; legal fiction.



I. INTRODUCTION:
Resumption of death penalty executions and confirmation of death penalty by High Court, in high profile case of blasphemy accused Asia Bibi has once again heightened the controversy that really started 7 years ago when Pakistan government imposed a moratorium on death penalty; whether to keep capital punishment on the Pakistan statute book?[1]

History of Pakistan would have been different had it abolished Death Penalty before 1979. Zulfiqar Ali Bhutto[2], the democratically elected Prime Minister of Pakistan, who was hanged in 1979 in a politically maneuvered decision,[3] would have been released after review of his case in 1988, when his ousting dictator General Zia ul Haq perished in an air crash and his daughter was elected as Prime Minister. Many people claim that Bhutto would have been to Pakistan what Nelson Mandela had been for South Africa and what Aung San Suu Kyi is for Myanmar; if, and only if, Pakistan did not have the harsh, brutal and irreversible penalty of killing people officially i.e., under the authority of law!
This Article looks at different philosophical, moral and utilitarian aspects of death penalty and sees whether it goes with our current values of collective conscience? Death penalty in many countries is awarded for a number of different crimes ranging from murder to blasphemy to rape. As a test case, this Article analyzes the justifiability of death penalty in cases of murder only. If death penalty cannot be justifiably awarded for murder, it cannot possibly be awarded for any other crime.
A large majority of Pakistanis believe that death penalty is not only a just punishment for murder it has most utility in terms of utility. They argue passionately that in our socio-economic conditions it is the only option available to keep an effective check on the homicide rate. It is the only punishment which creates special deterrent effect in the minds of the potential future murderers. Moreover, it is the only mode by which victim’s death can be retributed.
Relying heavily on the notion that knowledge is by no means a product of presumptions[4] and that truth lies in the mind of the beholder,[5] this paper analyzes viability of the major arguments in favour of retaining death penalty as a possible punishment for murder. Going one step further, the paper argues that legal, ideological and Constitutional obstacles in abolishing death penalty from Pakistani jurisprudence can be overcome by utilizing the age old tool of legal fiction.
To put the argument in perspective, the next section will take a glance over the creation and development of the concept of punishment in general.



II. PUNISHMENT & ITS EVOLUTION:
Conceptually speaking, punishment is a society’s reaction to crime.[6] It used to be official revenge on victim’s behave which later developed into a means to keep society safe of criminals: by reformation, isolation or execution. Claiming its justification originally from moral values, punishment, crossing the domain of divinity, landed in the realm of law. Law has its roots in the collective value system of the society.[7] In the form of written word of statutes and judicial decisions, law is the executed expression of society’s political decisions based on its collective conscience. But translation of political decisions of the society into executable legal decrees is not the only mode in which law functions. Many a times law can be used as a tool to bring change in social values. When some of society’s social values go rotten and require consciously engineered change, people who are placed by the society at the helm of its affairs are responsible to evaluate situations & issues rationally, and take pragmatic decisions leading to practical solutions, often violating and in the long run altering the social morality.
Historically, institution of punishment came into being with the formation of first formal societies; the tribes.[8] Benefits of keeping people together in shape of a tribal society gave rise to the need for social order. Backed by religion, institution of punishment became the foundational basis of tribal community’s peace & order. In those primitive societies, barring few punishments which prescribed on the basis of utility, rest were inflicted indirectly (by allowing the victim party to take its revenge) and were justified on the basis of retribution.[9] Gradually, with the advent of modern society and development of social contract theory, state usurped complete authority of deciding the quantum and mode of punishment along with the sole responsibility to inflict it. And so the rationality seeped in criminal law.[10]
Admittedly, the modern criminal legal system is not an end in itself but is simply a means to achieve peace and order in a society.[11] In contrast to ancient legal systems which were mainly based on the concepts of divine guidance and retribution, modern legal systems’ objectives of criminal law are to prevent the commission of crime, discouragement of the potential criminals and isolation of criminals from society in order to keep the community safe of them.[12] Thus, in terms of utility, punishments can aim for deterrence, isolation, reform, retribution or a combination of above.[13]
Converging the argument from justification of punishments in general to the justification of death penalty, next section is going to analyze the viability of the argument justifying state’s right to kill its citizens under the authority of its own laws.



III. PHILOSOPHICAL JUSTIFICATION OF STATE KILLING:
Even on the philosophical plane, it is very difficult to justify a state’s right to kill. The notion of a state having a right to kill provides no logical support to the notion that a state is right in killing.[14] Arguing otherwise is a sure trap to Petitio Principii. State gets right to kill simply by declaring so. The only condition on this unbridled power of the state is that this declaration should be made following the prescribed law making procedure. Thus a state would claim its right to kill as legal and valid if declaration to this effect has been made in accordance with the legal procedure. Therefore this killing right, although would have ample support of procedural compliance, would not be able to claim any moral or rational justification per se. The fact that a statute has been enacted by following the prescribed procedure correctly cannot justify the claim that it ‘should’ have been enacted in the first place.[15] So state’s justification to kill cannot be derived from legality or validly of its ‘death statutes’. It will have to be looked for in the depths of ethics and rationality.
One argument equates state and its citizen thereby holding that destroying state’s peace and order amounts to killing it; which grants the state a right to kill such criminal citizen in self defence. Even without going into the fallacy of equating state with its citizen, it is evident that an attempt to level state’s right of granting death penalty with a citizen’s right of self defense is naïve, to say the least. Citizens are given right to kill in self-defense on the basis of special circumstances where a citizen’s life comes under serious and imminent threat of being taken without the authority of law, where there is not enough time for law to take appropriate action, and where there is no alternative except to kill the attacker in order to save a life being taken unlawfully. Although a murderer violates the laws of the State and thus, in a sense, attacks its existence, neither such action poses any serious and imminent threat to State’s existence nor is there any shortage of very feasible alternatives.[16]
A powerful argument of retentionists’ is based on retribution; claim that emotional satisfaction of the victim’s family, by ding unto the criminal what he did unto the victim, is essential to attain social peace and ideal justice. Now if it is claimed that law wants to equal scores with the murderer on the basis of tit-for-tat, ideally speaking murderer should be awarded death penalty in exactly the same manner, however brutal and inhuman that may be, in which he had killed the victim.[17] But for that, civilization is claimed to have grown too mature.[18] A heavy weight view against retaining death penalty is that not only it psychologically places ‘killing in retribution’ on the legal plane,[19] it also lowers the moral code of the society resulting in extinguishing of community’s respect for life and brutalization of collective values of the society.[20]
Though punishment has always been a social necessity, and still remains so; death penalty, although has always been an essential, rather popular punishment in ancient legal systems, is no more essential. Proportionality and utility of punishment are at the base of contemporary legal systems; that is why mens rea is an essential element in modern concept of crime. It is utilized in order to objectively ascertain the intention and circumstances of the crime committed, so that accidental criminals can be suitably punished, mainly as a warning to them as well as others, and then assimilated back in the society while the habitual trouble makers can be marked and quarantined. Ancient mode of permanently getting rid of the dangerous trouble makers has always been execution. However, one rather humane way of keeping the society safe and free of trouble makers is to sentence them to long imprisonments, which can be made to last, say, till the natural death of the convict. In this respect, however, the argument for abolition of death penalty is not based on the ground of granting lesser penalty, since very long imprisonments, like the ones lasting till the natural death of the prisoner or comparable, can be anything but punishments ‘lesser’ than execution. The case for abolition of death penalty is also not based on the premise of having any kind of sympathy with the murderer, rather it is based on the concept that death penalty is no longer consistent with our self-respect.[21]
Recognition of global value against retention of death penalty is evident from the fact that more and more countries are abolishing it. Since the start of this millennium, at least 18 more countries have abolished death penalty from their law codes.[22] Moreover, even Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court and the Unites Nations Security Council resolutions establishing the International Criminal Tribunals for former Yugoslavia and Rwanda, though established to try most heinous crimes, do not allow infliction of death penalty on the convicts.[23]
Death penalty is a punishment which is irreversible immediately and completely and in case of conviction of an innocent, if discovered later on, there is no way of undoing the wrong, even in part. It was precisely for this reason that in the year 2003, Governor Ryan of the State of Illinois in the United States of America imposed a moratorium on the death penalty after discovering that 13 of the 167 convicts on the death row were innocent.[24] By any standard, there is more than fair chance that our system of criminal justice will produce a much better ratio of innocent convicts, if proper audits are carried out.
We do not allow abortion at any stage of the conception, although we are not sure at which stage life begins in the fetus, because we consider human life too sacred to be terminated unnaturally by humans. We do not allow euthanasia, although we may be certain that there is no chance of recovery and that patient is undergoing an agonizing torture, again because we consider human life too sacred. But we do not consider human life sacred enough to abolish death penalty and opt to continue to kill people, calculatedly and legally, basically for two reasons: firstly to do unto them what they have done unto others, and secondly, to ‘scare’ others. The chances of innocents being executed in this process by mistake are considered ‘collateral damage’!
After analyzing the concept of death penalty from philosophical angle and seeing if state can justifiably claim to have a right to kill its rowdy citizens, the next section will look at the issue empirically and will examine whether the experimental data supports the argument that death penalty in fact plays a role in lowering the homicide rate?


IV. UTILITY OF DEATH PENALTY:
Death is one of the oldest punishments in legal history. However, this reminiscence of the past is still very rampant in the modern day world. By the figures covering period up to 2010, criminal justice system of 102 nations of the world have death penalty for different crimes while 95 nations have abolished it.[25] This means that our globe, in terms of number of states, is roughly divided equally on the question of justifiability of death penalty. So here is a live and a lethal issue on which the world is divided equally. This sounds challenging; both ways!
Modern day proponents of death penalty invoke all the aims of punishments in their favour; all but one—reformation.
First of all it is claimed that death penalty is ‘the’ most effective deterrent against a crime, and thus is justified as an appropriate punishment for heinous crimes like murder. Thus, on the basis of utility it is the most useful and beneficial punishment for the greatest good of the greatest number of people in the society. This argument, strong as it is, has one inherent weakness; it is based on a premise that can be verified empirically. And so was it done, over and over again. The hypothesis: “Does death punishment provide a better deterrent to murder than long punishment?” was repeatedly verified by empirical data.[26]
Apparently there were some states imposing death penalty which had higher murder rate than those which had abolished it.[27] Moreover, many states in USA abolished death penalty and after few years re-introduced it. Therefore specific empirical studies were conducted on the reliable and comprehensive data. All the changes in homicide rate after abolition of death penalty and also after its re-introduction were duly recorded and scientifically studied. However, no deterrent effect of death penalty on homicide rate could be detected.[28] Even a niche argument that death penalty has special deterrent effect in cases of murder of police and prison staff, failed the scientific test.[29]
A critical study of data and methods used for extracting and verifying empirical evidence in support of deterrent effect of death penalty on homicide rate was conducted by Donohue and Wolfers concluding that death penalty is not a major influence on the murder rate of a state.[30]
In 1972 Federal Supreme Court of United States of America held that[31] death penalty was violative of U.S. Constitution. The view was over ruled by the Supreme Court in 1976. This period of unconstitutionality of death penalty provided remarkable opportunity to the researchers to collect data and scientifically study the deterrent effects of death penalty on murder rate.[32] Despite performing thorough statistical studies on the data for the period before 1972, when the death penalty was legal, from 1972 to 1976, when the death penalty was abolished, and for the period after 1976, when the death penalty was re-instated in those states, no evidence could be found to support the hypothesis that death penalty is more effective deterrent than long imprisonment sentences.[33]
This scenario, however, is not United States specific. For instance, Canada abolished death penalty in 1976 and in next 25 years its homicide rate fell to almost half. On the other hand, as of year 2000, homicide rate of USA, where in majority of states death penalty is applicable, was almost 3 times higher than Canada. Not only that, but European Union countries, where abolition of death penalty is a pre-condition to the join the Union, have much lower crime rate than USA.[34]
A very persuasive argument by the third world countries in favour of retaining death penalty is the difference of socio-economic conditions between developing and the developed nations. It is argued that due to difference of such socio-economic conditions, other penalties may have proved to be sufficient deterrence in developed nations but in developing countries death penalty is the only effective deterrent.[35] Nevertheless, in support of this argument no material from any country of the world including the developing ones, could ever be produced.[36]
Arguing for abolishment of death penalty does not mean that penalty for murder is to be made softer or lesser.[37] It is just a question of change of mode of punishment without compromising on its quantum, harshness or proportionality. As a matter of fact, the actual deterrence is the certainty in the mind of the criminal that he will be arrested, convicted and punished promptly; not that the punishment prescribed, however remote the possibility of its actual infliction may be, is harsh.[38] Thus it has been concluded by United States of America’s National Academy of Science that 10% increase in the probability of arrest and conviction would lower twice as many crimes as would be lowered by a similar increase in the severity of punishment.[39] Moreover, when state kills a person to deter others, it uses a human being as a tool to achieve its administrative goals. Such a calculated killing in cold blood, to serve state’s administrative objectives, strips the offender of his humanity and lowers the dignity of a human being to the scale of a mere tool.[40]
A valid question arises that if the empirical evidence is so clear that death penalty has no special deterrence against crime, why is it so difficult to convince peoples and authorities to abolish it? US Presidential election campaign for the year 2000 may shed some light on this phenomenon. In the earlier part of the year 2000, US Attorney General Janet Reno stated, “I have inquired for most of my adult life about studies that might show that the death penalty is a deterrent, and I have not seen any research that would substantiate that point.” However, later that year, in Presidential debates, George W. Bush stated that death penalty “saves other peoples’ lives.”[41] Thus the political questions which need to be settled by public through vote are still settled by popular slogans and presumptive beliefs, without least reference to the empirical evidence or logical arguments.
Another argument in favour of retaining death penalty is retribution. Vengeance is one of the basic human instincts, much like love, they say. Therefore, in order to satisfy the basic emotional need of the victim’s family, punishment should be inflicted on the criminal to avenge the crime. In case of murder, therefore, vengeance demands that murderer should be murdered to keep the scores even. Powerful though it is, this argument confuses positive and negative human instincts. In addition, it ignores thousands of years of development of human conscience, social values and human civilization. Death penalty is a fossilized punishment of an ancient system of criminal administration of justice based on vengeance. Civilized justice has arisen above this outmoded and brutal notion of retribution by adopting symbolic yet proportional punishments[42] which need not repeat the crime for doing complete justice.[43]
The point here is not to deny the righteous anger of the murder victim’s family or abhorrence of society for this heinous crime, but to stress that capital punishment is not the only appropriate way available to the society for expression of its moral outrage at this vile crime. We neither put out the eyes of a criminal who has blinded another nor sentence the rapist to undergo rape. “The state does not need to engage in the cold and calculated killing of murderers in order to express moral outrage at their conduct. A very long prison sentence is also a way of expressing outrage and visiting retribution upon the criminal.”[44]
Although retribution does not make a powerful argument for the biblical notion of an eye for an eye, it does make a good case for a proportionally harsh sentence. But an argument for abolition of death penalty is never based on getting soft on the murderer notion. It will be hard to argue that a sentence of 100 years of rigorous imprisonment would in any way be less harsh than death penalty, for instance.
Lastly comes the case of isolation. The oldest argument employed in support of death penalty by the ancient tribal societies, other than God’s injunction, was hygiene. Offenders were considered filth to be permanently removed from the society. In times when human intellect had not created institution of prison, death penalty would have been the only way to attain this goal. However, very long prison sentence can provide a viable alternate to achieve this end in the modern day system of administration of justice. A need to permanently eliminate a murderer from society can be achieved by putting him in prison, permanently.
After dealing with conceptual basis of the argument, and before indulging into the issues involved in the Pakistani jurisprudence of capital punishment, next section will take the overview of death penalty jurisprudence in European Union and United States of America.

V. EUROPEAN UNION AND UNITED STATES OF AMERICA:
In Pakistan, it is a general perception that Western world is itself convinced of the utility of retaining death penalty but push third world countries, especially the Islamic countries and specifically Pakistan to abolish it, in order to create anarchy therein. Therefore it would be useful to see what exactly is the stance versus situation of the European Union and specially United States of America to understand whether they are justified in lobbying for abolition of death penalty or are they simply using it as a tool to put pressure on other countries for some covert purposes?
The position of European Union is clear; it encourages states to the point of pushing for abolition of death penalty because it has abolished it on the ground of being immoral, brutal and below human dignity.[45]
The position of United States of America, however, is complicated. While USA campaigns for abolition of death penalty, in majority of its constituting states[46] death penalty is legal. In USA authority to legalize death penalty or to abolish it lies with the legislatures of its federating states. Only condition on them is that it should not violate any provision of federal Constitution. A question came up before the federal Supreme Court of USA in 1972 as to whether the imposition of capital punishment amounts to cruel and unusual punishment, which has specifically been prohibited by the Constitution of USA.[47] Holding that death penalty was an awesome punishment, US Supreme Court held it violative of the federal Constitution in the manner in which it was being executed.[48] However, in the 1976 case[49] US Supreme Court, in the background of a nationwide reaction to the Furman Case,[50] over-ruled that decision and held that if a state decides to legalize death penalty with some procedural checks, then the death penalty will not be violative of the US Constitution.[51] While political support shown by the majority of Americans in favour of retaining death penalty is often cited as the major factor behind US Supreme Court’s over-ruling Furman Case[52] in its Gregg judgment of 1976,[53] there is a strong possibility of another very dangerous factor, and that is mis-representation of empirical evidence.
When in its 1972 Furman decision[54] US Supreme Court held that the then existing state statutes providing death penalty were violative of US Constitution, Isaac Ehrlich published his analysis of national time series data claiming that his analysis proved that each death penalty saved 8 lives by creating a very special deterrent effect which no other punishment was able to produce. Solicitor General pleading in US Supreme Court next year, for a decision in favour of death penalty, in Gregg’s case[55] did cite Ehrlich’s analysis as a piece of scientific evidence proving utility of death penalty. It is claimed that this must have a persuasive effect on the Supreme Court. However, as the situation unfolded, Ehrlich’s analysis was found incorrect and this led to US National Academy of Sciences to issue its 1978 report clarifying that there was no valid empirical evidence to support special deterrent effect of death penalty.[56] Although all the empirical evidence collected by the US intelligentsia points towards the non-existence of any special deterrent effect of death penalty and it is making a case for abolition at home and abroad, the popular belief there still is that it does. So death penalty in US has two faces: popular and intellectual. While the popular belief in US is still faithful to the divine utility of the biblical notion of an eye for an eye, the rationally considered opinion is striving hard to claim its place in the social horizon. In the back drop of popular political rhetoric, to say the least, this sounds familiar in Pakistani situation as well.
The next section will now take a look at the law and the facts and figures in Pakistan in relation to death penalty. The arguments that are advanced by the fundamentalist/conservative faction of religious scholars in favour of death penalty will also be examined before taking up the task of suggesting the possible ways to wriggle out of the situation without really getting into it.


VI. PAKISTAN & ISLAM:
In 2006, due to negligence of the registrar’s office, appellate court’s orders of suspension of death penalty of a convict were not transmitted to the jail authorities. The man was hanged from the neck till death while the court was preparing to check the genuineness of his guilt.[57] The country in which this poor man was hanged mistakenly, is Pakistan; a country which ranks among the countries of the world with highest death penalty awarding ratio.[58]
As of June, 2012, some 8,500 persons were on the death row in Pakistan.[59] While at the time of creation of Pakistan in 1947 only homicide and treason were punishable with death; today there are more than two dozen crimes which carry death penalty, including sabotage of railway system,[60] blasphemy, stripping a woman of her clothes in public, etc.[61] This is a country which, except for few procedural and formal amendments, has not changed the basic structure of the legal system that it inherited from its colonial masters.[62] Pakistani society has been criticized even otherwise for not showing any substantial progress since its independence some 7 decades ago.[63] A country adversely affected by botched police investigations and unfair trials[64] where only 1.5 murder trial judges are available for 100,000 people,[65] there always is an extremely high probability of miscarriage of justice. Yet, in Pakistan, pleading for abolition of death penalty is not only difficult, it’s actually dangerous. Pakistani pro-death penalty voices, which are often aggressive and usually fundamentalist, invoke Islamic law, retribution and deterrence, in order of priority, as the justification of penalty of death.
While the rationality of historical trends indicates that a considerable portion of Islamic law was developed very progressively by the Islamic scholars[66] on utilitarian basis, very pragmatically,[67] it was only in later centuries that religious fanaticism seeped in and the whole system based on dynamism and innovation was frozen in the medieval space-time. Today there certainly is a dire need to develop Islamic law on modern lines as is being done in some other Islamic countries,[68] but such trends, arguments and needs are conveniently denied by many in Pakistan, for the most part on the strength of religious fundamentalism. Even the argument that bulk of Pakistani law has been very progressively developed and the trend should be continued, for instance, where it provides prison sentence for theft while in Islamic law punishment for theft is cutting of a hand,[69] falls on deaf ears. Their simple yet powerful rhetoric is that biblical notion of an eye for an eye is part of Islamic law which, according to the Constitution,[70] is the supreme law of the land. Thus death penalty for a murderer is ordained by God and God’s injunction is based on the utility of retribution and deterrence. Although it is not only difficult, but is actually dangerous in Pakistan now-a-days to question the religious fanatics’ distorted argument of the divine wisdom, yet there is a very strong and persuasive logic against this age old rhetoric of ideological fundamentalism. In Islamic law, in case of murder, there is a possibility for the murderer of paying monetary compensation in lieu of death penalty. This possibility available for a rich murder convict of buying out his life and in fact all the punishment and going scot-free the moment he pays the blood money, destroys the fanatics’ arguments of both retribution and deterrence[71] and should have forced them to seriously consider the possibility of replacing death penalty with some other proportionate penalty. But the dead-end response from this quarter is always based on the notion of religion being a phenomenon beyond and above reason.
The next section will consider the ideological as well as constitutional checks that are the actual jurisprudential challenges to abolition of death penalty and will also suggest a possible solution to overcome these checks by differentiating legal death from medical death and using legal fiction to replace medical executions by legal executions.


VII. LEGAL FICTION—MEDICAL DEATH VS. LEGAL DEATH:
In Pakistan death sentence cannot be abolished easily even if it is accepted that it should be. There are checks stronger than the ones which can be overcome by simple legislation; Constitutional and ideological checks. The Preamble of the Constitution[72] makes is abundantly clear that the Sovereignty in Pakistan’s legal system belongs to God alone. This settles the ideological formation providing the fundamental basis to the Constitutional structure of this first modern ideological state of the world. Not only this ideological basis is expressed in its name viz., Islamic Republic of Pakistan[73] but also in the operative Articles of its Constitution. Thus Article 2-A of the Constitution makes the concept and claims enshrined in the Preamble of the Constitution as integral part of the Constitution.[74] Article 2 sets it abundantly clear that Pakistan is not a secular state but has a religion. Consequently, Constitution declares that Islam is the State religion of Pakistan[75] while it also defines who is a Muslim and who is a non-Muslim.[76] The matter does not end here. Seven years after enactment of the Constitution, it was amended and a precise and very elaborate mechanism was added in the Constitution, by creating a special limb of higher judiciary with specific and exclusive jurisdiction to declare all the laws which are in conflict with Islamic laws as null and void and non-existent.[77] Since death penalty is an integral part of the Islamic law, its abolition by simple legislation will violate the express provisions of the Constitution. So in Pakistan death penalty cannot be abolished simply by amending statutes, it requires Constitutional amendment. However, this problem cannot be solved by amendment of Constitution even as such an amendment will violate the basic structure[78] and the very ideological and foundational basis of the Constitution. Supreme Court of Pakistan has held that the Constitution of Pakistan is more than a random, or even serial and somewhat systematic compilation of articles; rather it is not only a structured document but a document based on a well defined structure. One integral and a significant part, a salient feature, of this structure—the basis structure of the Constitution—comprises of different articles spread all over the Constitution imparting Islamic theme therein. And this ‘salient feature’ cannot be amended by the assembly even if it follows the procedure provided in the Constitution itself for its amendment. The Supreme Court has held this and this is good law in Pakistan. Now this ‘is’ a problem!
Such problems arise seldom from the internal conflict in a legal system but usually when there is a conflict between a dogmatized legal system and the development of dynamic collective conscience beyond that dogmatized system. It is the problems like these that have been arising in different legal systems of the world, challenging the jurists in history and shook them out of their deep slumbers of following the traditions and forced them to come up with new and innovative responses. Such had always been the out of the box responses aimed at meeting the social requirements which the legal system of the time had failed to come up to. One such innovative response had been tackling of such complex and insurmountable problem by creating legal fictions.
A legal fiction is simply a false statement recognized as having utility.[79] Thus it were somewhat similar situations which led the jurists to create legal fictions like a distinct legal entity of a corporation where a non-entity gets entity by sheer force of law. Similar is the English concept of adoption where legal fiction replaces adopted parents as natural parents. Law takes control of the situation where it decides to create legal fiction for the betterment of the society and designs the scenario, not according to reality, but in accordance with socio-legal requirements. Thus, law creates an artificial distinction between natural person and legal person and declares to have granted the status of legal person to a corporation by operation of legal fiction. Same can be the case with the concept of death.
One constructive way of using legal fiction can be to distinguish between medical death and legal death and replacing all death penalties with legal deaths instead of medical deaths. This should not be too fictitious in the face of modern thinking where there is a dire need to abolish old concepts of death and come up with new ones in the backdrop of modern scientific and technological advances and controversies.[80] A recent study in the adequacy of traditional definitions of medical death has concluded that in view of development in medical science a statutory definition is essentially required to replace the traditional definition of medical death, which is no more adequate amidst modern views of life and death.[81] A very convenient way of grasping the concept is by visualizing coma patients. A person in coma, although is alive medically, is practically dead. Similarly, a person locked up in a cage for the rest of his life can be seen as essentially, or to look at it more precisely, socially dead! This will mean that law will consider a certain kind of limited rights to life as a person’s legal death, which can be awarded and executed without killing that person biologically. Thus, if life of a person, in jail, is termed no-life legally, an imprisonment sentence till his natural biological death becomes his legal death. So the day a person is put in prison never to be taken out alive, becomes the day of his legal death. Such creation of a legal fiction of ‘legal death’ to replace ‘medical death’ for the purposes of punishment will solve both angles of the challenge. As Constitutional frame work does not allow abolition of death penalty, it will not be abolished and deserving convicts will continue to be awarded the penalty of death; penalty of ‘legal death’ to be precise. And since no human life will be terminated by the state as a punishment, there neither will be any degradation of collective values of the society nor will there be any possible innocent executions. If otherwise false statements can be legally taken as true in order to safeguard commercial and social relations, why can’t same thing be done in order to save precious human lives?


VIII. CONCLUSION:
From the brutal ancient concepts of crucifying people in order to give them exemplary punishments, human intellect grew up and matured. The basis of social relations developed from narrowly perceived personal self-interests to collective good of the greatest possible number of people. The basis of law out grown the divine wisdom and entered the era of utilitarian laws. Punishments also left the times of emotional satisfaction and personal vengeance and entered the period of pragmatism. Man started asking if it is alright for a non-victim party like state, to take revenge as an agent? And even if it is alright, is it justifiable to kill a human being on that account? Then the question of scaring potential law breakers by killing people arose. People started thinking if it is just to kill one person to scare another? And further questions were asked; Does killing of a murderer by the state has some special deterrent effect as compared to alternate but proportionally harsh punishment? And it was also asked if the only way to keep a trouble maker out of a society is to murder him under the authority of law?
Philosophical deliberations were made on these issues for centuries and in the last several decades, scientific investigations were also conducted to see the empirical evidence supporting these questioned concepts and purposes. The answers that came are over whelming and against death penalty. The question then turned to chalking out some strategy to get the society out of the clutches of its fossilized legal and moral concepts, which it failed to do in its own course of intellectual maturity, and get the death penalty abolished in law. This proved to be a tricky task. While in modern western secular states it requires only a public mobilization and convincing majority of voters, in religious and ideological states like Pakistan it proved to be a task much more difficult. Here, even if the dominant public opinion is developed in favour of abolition of death penalty, it cannot be expressed and executed legally without hitting the very foundational and ideological structure of the state. Thus a technical solution is prescribed. The solution is to use the concept of legal fiction to make a distinction between the concepts of medical and legal deaths. This will serve two purposes: first, it will provide a very harsh punishment to a murderer which will not only satisfy the vengeance needs of the victim’s family but will also provide enough deterrence to the potential murderers, and second, it will save the brutality of state calculatedly killing a human being under the authority of law. Not only will this stop the official murders at the hands of state, it will be done without violating the ideological basis of the ideological states. Among many other purposes that it will serve, will be a possibility of undoing a wrong committed to an innocent convict, as no realistic system of administration of justice to date ensures error free convictions.





* Author is Advocate Supreme Court of Pakistan.
[1] (a)-Daily the Dawn, dated December 17th, 2014. Available at: http://www.dawn.com/news/1151408/nawaz-removes-moratorium-on-death-penalty. Accessed on 20.04.2015.
“ISLAMABAD: Prime Minister Nawaz Sharif on Wednesday approved the removal of moratorium on death penalty after the [Taliban] carnage in Peshawar [School] killed 141 people [mostly school boys].”

(b)-Daily the Dawn, dated October 17, 2014. Available at: http://www.dawn.com/news/1138402. Accessed on 05.11.2014.
“LAHORE: The Lahore High Court (LHC) on Thursday upheld the death sentence of a Christian woman convicted of blasphemy four years ago, as her lawyers vowed to appeal.
Asia Bibi, a mother of five, has been on death row since November 2010 after she was found guilty of making derogatory remarks about the Holy Prophet Mohammed (peace be upon him) during an argument with a Muslim woman.
Two high-profile politicians – then Punjab governor Salmaan Taseer and minorities minister Shahbaz Bhatti – were murdered in 2011 after calling for reforms to the blasphemy law and describing Bibi's trial as flawed.”



“ISLAMABAD: The PML-N-PPP appeasement policy towards convicted terrorists, target killers, rapists and those involved in other heinous crimes because of the continued moratorium on the death penalty is said to be the major cause for the rise in major crimes and terrorism in the country.

Rangers, police, other law-enforcement agencies and even the judiciary have been repeatedly calling for an end to the moratorium on the death penalty but for the past six years neither the previous PPP government nor the present PML-N government lifted the informal ban placed in September 2008.

This moratorium on the death penalty is not only in violation of the law, but is also un-Islamic. The security forces personnel are of the firm opinion that this moratorium has badly hurt the much-needed factor of deterrence against crime in Pakistan, where heinous crime is on the rise.”

[2] Father of former Pakistani Prime Minister Benazir Bhutto.
[3] International Federation for Human Rights & Human Rights Commission of Pakistan, Report Mission of Investigation, Slow March to the gallows, Death Penalty in Pakistan, 2007, 17. Available at: http://www.fidh.org/IMG/pdf/Pakistan464angconjointpdm.pdf/. Accessed on: 17th August, 2014.
“The most famous death row inmate, former Prime Minister Zulfiqar Ali Bhutto, was executed on 4 April 1979 on the charge of conspiring to murder a political opponent, after what was widely held to be an unfair and politicized trial. Bhutto’s appeal to the Supreme Court was rejected by 4 judges out of 7; one of the 4 stated in hindsight that the death penalty should not have been awarded, and that he regretted his decision to condemn Bhutto to death, which was due mainly to the massive pressure he had been subjected to.”
[4] Steven Connor, Postmodernist Culture, An Introduction to Theories of the Contemporary, Blackwell, 1989 reprint 1994, 3,
“Knowledge, it is often claimed, can only be gained and enjoyed about what is in some sense over and done with.”
[5] Slavoj Zizek, Living in the End Times, Verso, 2010, xiv,
“Though one may be tempted to oppose these perspectives—the dogmatism of blind faith versus an openness towards the unexpected—one should nevertheless insist on the truth contained in the second version: truth, as opposed to knowledge, is, like a Badiouian Even, something that only an engaged gaze, the gaze of a subject who “believes in it,” is able to see.”
[6] Edwin H. Sutherland & Donald R. Cressey, Criminology (J.B. Lippincott Company, 1978) 301.
[7] Al Gore, The Future, WH Allen, 2014, 363,
“Behaviors that bring rewards become more common. Those that don’t diminish. The elements of our nature that are activated by rewarded behaviors gain strength. Social groups establish values that reflect both the behaviors they wish to reward and those they want to discourage. These values become embedded in tribes, communities, nations, economic systems, institutions, and cultures.”
[8] Supra, note 6, 305-308.
[9] Katherine S. Williams, Textbook on Criminology, 3rd ed, Blackstone Press Limited, 1997, 1.
[10] Ibid, 1.
[11] J.C. Smith & Brian Hogan, Criminal Law, Butterworth & Co. (Publishers) Ltd, 7th ed, 1992, 3.
[12] Ibid, 3.
[13] Ibid, 4.
[14]Hugo Adam Bedau, Death is Different: Studies in the Morality, Law, and Politics of Capital Punishment, Boston, Northeastern University Press, 1987, 46-63. Quoted in Joel Feinberg & Hyman Gross (ed), Philosophy of Law, Wadsworth Publishing Company, 1975, 4th ed, 1991, 778.
[15] Ibid, 778.
[16] Ibid, 781-782.
[17] Ibid, 786.
[18] The State Vs. T Makwanyane and M Mchunu, Constitutional Court of the Republic of South Africa, Case No. CCT/3/94, decided on 06.06.1995, Para-233. Available at: http://www.saflii.org/za/cases/ZACC/1995/3.html. Accessed on: 17th August, 2014.
[19] John Lamperti, Ph.D., Does Capital Punishment Deter Murder? A Brief Look at the Evidence, 2010, 8. Available at: https://www.math.dartmouth.edu/~lamperti/my%20DP%20paper,%20current%20edit.htm. Accessed on: 17th August, 2014.
[20] Furman Vs. Georgia, United States Supreme Court, 1972, 408 U.S. 238 (1972). Quoted in Joel Feinberg & Hyman Gross (ed), Philosophy of Law, Wadsworth Publishing Company, 1975, 4th ed, 1991, 766.
[21] Supra, note 18, Para-189.
[22] International Commission against the Death Penalty, The death penalty and the “most serious crimes”, A country by country overview of the death penalty in law and practice in retentionist states, January, 2013, 7. Available at: http://www.icomdp.org/cms/wp-content/uploads/2013/02/Most-serious-crimes_final_6Feb2013.pdf. Accessed on: 20th August, 2014.
[23] Supra, note 3, 10.
[24] Ibid, 9.
[25] David Garland, Why Does the U.S. Have Capital Punishment? Published 2012, 2. Available at: http://photos.state.gov/libraries/amgov/133183/english/P_You_Asked_WhyCapitalPunishment_English.pdf. Accessed on: 17th August, 2014.
[26] Supra, note 19, 1.
[27] Ibid, 3.
[28] Ibid, 4.
[29] Baily & Peterson, Murder, Capital Punishment and deterrence: a review of the evidence and an examination of police killings, Journal of Social Issues, 1994, 53-74. Quoted in John Lamperti, Ph.D., Does Capital Punishment Deter Murder? A Brief Look at the Evidence, 2010, 5. Available at: https://www.math.dartmouth.edu/~lamperti/my%20DP%20paper,%20current%20edit.htm. Accessed on: 17th August, 2014.
[30] John J. Donohue and Justin Wolfers, Uses and Abuses of Empirical Evidence in the Death Penalty Debate, 58 Stanford Law Review, 791-846, 2006, 841.
[31] Details below
[32] Tammra Hunt, Does Death Penalty Deter Murder? Research Methods in Economics, Fall 2004, 8. Available at: http://www.bus.ucf.edu/faculty/rhofler/file.axd?file=2011%2F2%2FHunt-Death+penalty.pdf. Accessed on: 17th August, 2014.
[33] Ibid, 13.
[34] Supra, note 3, 8.
[35] Supra, note 18, Para-116.
[36] Ibid, Para-146.
[37] Ibid, Para-123.
[38] Ibid, Para-122.
[39] Supra, note 3, 8.
[40] Supra, note 18, Para-316.
[41] John J. Donohue and Justin Wolfers, The Death Penalty: No Evidence for Deterrence, The Berkeley Electronic Press, Economists’ voice, 2006, 1. Available at: http://www.deathpenaltyinfo.org/DonohueDeter.pdf. Accessed on: 17th August, 2014.
[42] Supra, note 3, 9.
[43] Supra, note 18, Para-197.
[44] Ibid, Para-129.
[45] Supra, note 3, 8.
[46] 37 States by the figures of 2008.
[47] Furman Vs. Georgia, United States Supreme Court, 1972, 408 U.S. 238 (1972).
[48] Furman Vs. Georgia, United States Supreme Court, 1972, 408 U.S. 238 (1972). Quoted in Joel Feinberg & Hyman Gross (ed), Philosophy of Law, Wadsworth Publishing Company, 1975, 4th ed, 1991, 764.
[49] Gregg Vs. Georgia, United States Supreme Court (1976), 428 U.S. 153.
[50] Supra, note 47.
[51] Gregg Vs. Georgia, United States Supreme Court (1976), 428 U.S. 153. Quoted in Joel Feinberg & Hyman Gross (ed), Philosophy of Law, Wadsworth Publishing Company, 4th ed, 1991, 772.
“The most marked indication of society’s endorsement of the death penalty for murder is the legislative response to Furman. The legislatures of at least 35 states have enacted new statutes that provide for the death penalty for at least some crimes that result in the death of another person. And the congress of the United States, in 1974, enacted a statute providing the death penalty for aircraft piracy that results in death……But all the post-Furman statutes make clear that capital punishment itself has not been rejected by the elected representatives of the people.
In the only statewide referendum occurring since Furman and brought to our attention, the people of California adopted a Constitutional amendment that authorized capital punishment, in effect negating a prior ruling by the Supreme Court of California…..that the death penalty violated the California Constitution.”
[52] Supra, note 47.
[53] Supra, note 25, 3.
[54] Supra, note 47.
[55] Supra, note 49.
[56] Supra, note 30, 792.
[57] Supra, note 3, 18.
[58] Ibid, 16.
[59] Supra, note 22, 27.
[60] Supra, note 3, 17.
[61] Pakistan Penal Code, 1860, S. 295-C: “Whoever by words, either spoken or written, or by visible representation, or by any imputation, innuendo, or insinuation, directly or indirectly, defiles the sacred name of the Holy Prophet Muhammad (peace be upon him) shall be punished with death, or imprisonment for life, and shall also be liable to fine.”
S. 354-A: “Whoever assaults or uses criminal force to any woman and strips her of her clothes, and in that condition, exposes her to the public view, shall be punished with death or with imprisonment for life, and shall also be liable to fine.”
[62] Osama Siddique, Pakistan’s Experience with Formal Law, An Alien Justice, (Cambridge University Press, 2014), 8.
“If Jeremy Bentham’s preserved, albeit headless, body at University College London—the so called “Auto-icon”—was to be miraculously resurrected and induced to visit a contemporary Pakistani Court, he would be well within his rights to feel a certain sense of de ja vu. After all, he famously prophesied acting as the “dead legislative” of British India, with James Mill acting as its “living executive.” If his brilliant disciple Thomas Babington Macaulay were persuaded to undertake a similar escapade, he would be somewhat taken aback. He would discover that his great handiwork, the Indian Penal Code of 1860, is still en vogue, its original spirit intact beneath the veneer of periodic piecemeal amendments. Both time travelers could be excused for thinking that they had not travelled at all.”
[63] Ilhan Niaz, The Culture of Power and Governance of Pakistan 1947—2008, Oxford University Press, 2010, ed. 2011, ix.
“One went so far as to declare that if we were to take away the much derided ‘colonial legacy’ all that we would be left with are shrines, some palaces and a few cultural and aesthetic refinements.”
[64] Supra, note 3, 6.
[65] Supra, note 62, 20.
[66] N.J. Coulson, A History of Islamic Law, Edinburgh University Press, 1964, 1st Indian Reprint, Universal Law Publishing Co. Pvt Ltd, 1997, 50
“A conservative attachment to tradition is the hallmark of the early Medinan jurists, while their Kufan colleagues, living in a newly formed society which had no such roots in the past, were animated by a spirit of free enquiry and speculation.”
Noel J. Coulson, Conflicts and Tensions in Islamic Jurisprudence, The University of Chicago Press, 1969, 4
“The first 150 years of Islam were characterized by an almost untrammeled freedom of juristic reasoning in the solution of problems not specifically regulated by divine revelation. Such rules of law as the Qura’n and the sunna established were regarded simply as ad hoc modifications of the existing customary law. This existing law remained the accepted standard of conduct unless it was expressly superseded in some particular by the dictates of divine revelation. And when new circumstances posed new problems, these were answered on the basis simply of what seemed the most proper solution to the individual judge or jurist concerned. In the expression of his personal opinion, known ra’y, the individual was free to take into account any factors he deemed relevant. In short, in these early days law had a distinctly dual basis. It was a compound of the two separate spheres of the divine ordinance and the human decision.”
[67] Joseph Schacht, An Introduction to Islamic Law, Oxford University Press, 1964, 1st Indian Reprint, Universal Law Publishing Co. Pvt. Ltd, 1997, 15
“In the field of penal law, the first caliphs went beyond the sanctions enacted in the Koran by punishing with flogging, for instance, the authors of satirical poems directed against rival tribes, a form of poetic expression common in ancient Arabia.”
[68] Ran Hirschl, The New Constitution and the Judicialization of Pure Politics World Wide, 75 Fordham Law Review, 2006, 721-753, 737-738
“Another telling example of judicial articulation of a nation’s core values is the central role played by Egypt’s Supreme Constitutional Court in dealing with the core question of the status of Shari’a rules—arguably the most controversial and fundamental collective identity issue troubling the Egyptian polity. Since the 1979 establishment of judicial review in Egypt and the 1980 constitutional amendment that made Islamic Shari’a the principal source of legislation in that country, the court has increasingly been called upon to determine the constitutionality of legislative and administrative acts on the basis of their adherence to the principles of the Shari’a. “The question before the Court in all of these cases has been which principles of the Shari’a possess determinative and absolute authority.”
To address this question in a moderate way, the court developed a complex interpretative matrix of religious directives—the first of its kind by a nonreligious tribunal. It departed from the ancient traditions of the fiqh (Islamic jurisprudence or the cumulative knowledge/science of studying the Shari’a) schools, and has instead developed a new framework for interpreting the Shari’a. Specifically, the court has developed a flexible, modernist approach to interpreting the Shari’a that distinguishes between “unalterable and universally binding principles, and malleable applications of those principles.” Legislation that contravenes a strict, unalterable principle is declared unconstitutional and void, while at the same time, ijtihad (contemplation or external interpretation) is permitted in cases of textual lacunae, or where the pertinent rules are vague or open-ended. Furthermore, the government has been given broad legislative discretion in policy areas where the Shari’a is found to provide unclear or multiple answers, provided that that legislative outcome does not contravene the general spirit of the Shari’a. This interpretative approach has marked a true shift in the paradigm for legitimizing government policies based upon a moderate, fairly liberal interpretation (ijtihad) of the Shair’a.”
[69] Holy Quran, English translation by Marmaduke Pickthall (Pak Company, Lahore Pakistan, 2005), Chapter 5 (The Table Spread) Verse 38: “As for the thief, both the male and female, cut off their hands. It is the reward of their own deeds, an exemplary punishment from Allah. And Allah is Mighty, Wise.”
Pakistan Penal Code, 1860, Sec. 379: “Whoever commits theft shall be punished with imprisonment of either description for a term which may extend to three years, or with fine, or with both.”
[70] Constitution of Islamic Republic of Pakistan, 1973, Article 2: “Islam shall be the State religion of Pakistan.”
Article 203-D (3): “If any law or provision of law is held by the Court to be repugnant to the Injunctions of Islam,
(b) Such law or provision shall, to the extent to which it is held to be so repugnant, cease to have effect on the day on which the decision of the Court takes effect.”
[71] Supra, note 3, 20.
[72] Constitution of Islamic Republic of Pakistan, 1973, Preamble, “Whereas sovereignty over the entire Universe belongs to Almighty Allah alone……..”
[73] Constitution of Islamic Republic of Pakistan, 1973, Article 1(1): “Pakistan shall be a Federal Republic to be known as the Islamic Republic of Pakistan, hereinafter referred to as Paksitan.”
[74] Constitution of Islamic Republic of Pakistan, 1973, Article 2-A: “The principles and provisions set out in the Objectives Resolution reproduced in the Annex are hereby made substantive part of the Constitution and shall have effect accordingly.” The Preamble of the Constitution is derived from this Objectives Resolution.
[75] Constitution of Islamic Republic of Pakistan, 1973, Article 2: “Islam shall be the State religion of Pakistan.”
[76] Constitution of Islamic Republic of Pakistan, 1973, Article 260(3).
[77] Constitution of Islamic Republic of Pakistan, 1973, Article 203D(3): “If any law or provision of law is held by the Court to be repugnant to the Injunctions of Islam,
(b) Such law or provision shall, to the extent to which it is held to be so repugnant, cease to have effect on the day on which the decision of the Court takes effect.”
[78] Mahmood Khan Achakzai Vs. Federation of Pakistan, Supreme Court of Pakistan, PLD 1997 SC 426, 459
“……freedom bestowed upon the Parliament in clause (6) of Article 239 after amendment does not include power to amend those provisions of the Constitution by which would be altered salient features of the Constitution, namely federalism, Parliamentary Form of Government blended with Islamic provisions. As long as these salient features reflected in the Objectives Resolution are retained and not altered in substance, amendments can be made as per procedure prescribed in Article 239 of the Constitution.”
[79] Nancy J. Knauer, Legal Fictions and Juristic Truth, St. Thomas Law Review, Vol. 23, 2010, 4.
[80] Stuart J. Youngner, Robert M. Arnold & Renie Schaprio (ed), The Definition of Death, Contemporary Controversies, The John Hopkins University Press, 1999, xiii
[81] President’s Commission for the Study of Ethical Problems in Medicine and Biomedical and Behavioral Research, Defining Death, A Report on the Medical, Legal and Ethical Issues in the Determination of Death, 1981. Available at: https://repository.library.georgetown.edu/bitstream/handle/10822/559345/defining_death.pdf?sequence=1. Accessed on: 23rd August, 2014.

No comments:

Post a Comment